A False Antithesis
The Speaker, December 28, 1901
CULTURE AND RESTRAINT. By Hugh Black. London: Hodder and Stoughton. 6s.
Mr. Hugh Black, in his work on Culture and Restraint,
raises again the question of that great struggle between
the ideal of self-development and the ideal of self-restraint which has been so much discussed and
which may even at some time or other have existed.
But philosophers have talked a great deal too much
as if there were some kind of fundamental opposition
between pleasing others and pleasing oneself, as if
they were not both, under any tolerably suitable circumstances, exceedingly natural things to do. A man who
really set before himself a purely egotistic ideal would have
to lacerate himself like a monk. As other men crush down
vices he would have to crush down the ancient and rebellious virtues. In order to love himself only, he would have
to seek some darker and more illimitable deserts than the
hermits sought, that they might love God only. He would
have to turn his face from a man as St. Anthony turned his
face from a woman.
This is the first and most elementary of the modifications which may be suggested in the idea of Mr. Hugh
Black's book, the idea of an inevitable and fundamental
struggle between culture and restraint. For if culture be,
as its name implies, the making possible of the greatest
fruitfulness of this human spirit, it cannot be opposed to
religion or to altruism, or to anything under the sun. The
truth is that the word culture is used with an even
more grotesque narrowness than the word religion. A
cultured person in ordinary modern language means a person who is cultured in three or four of the most trivial and
uninteresting of the externals of life. But it is quite clear
that if the current exponent of culture despises the religious
instinct, sneers at popular sentiment, shrinks from the rude
contact of humanity, he does all this, not because he is
irreligious or immoral or egotistical, but simply because he
is uncultured. If a man cannot enjoy a crowd eating
oranges outside the gallery of a Surrey theatre, he is not a
cultured man. If a poet living in the country saw no
charms in the pig-sty, the farmer would be fully justified in
lamenting his lack of culture. For if culture be self-development it must include the simpler as well as the subtler
appetites and faculties, physical courage, family affection,
political excitement, a capacity for romping, and a sympathy
with the Salvation Army. We do not speak of the perfect
culture of a piece of ground when it could not possibly grow
corn, but could only grow chrysanthemums.
To begin with, therefore, it must be denied that culture
excludes religion; if it does it is not insufficient as religion,
it is insufficient as culture. The man who has learnt the
beauty of Maeterlinck's poetry and Morris's wall-papers
still requires, that he may complete his culture, to be taught
the beauty of a brass band and the poetry of Evangelical
hymns. But, on the other side, the case is quite equally
strong in regard to religion. Religion is, like culture, a
universal thing; it sums up the world, and, under whatever
temporary clouds of ethical error, it sums it up as a good
thing. Mr. Black adopts the generally-admitted classification, and pits Hellenism, as the representative of the idea of
enjoyment, against Hebraism as the representative of the
idea of repression. But whence did this wild distinction
come? Whence did the modern aesthetes get the astonishing idea that the Greeks were opposed to morality and
restraint? Were there ever people who moralised so much
as the Greek poets and philosophers? The neo-Pagan may
be a very brilliant and happy person, with his theories of
complete self-assertion and the law of the joy of life, and
there is nothing, in this connection, to be said about him,
except that almost any actual Pagan would have kicked him
out of his house. The aesthete who combines aesthetic culture and moral lawlessness may be a very good neo-Pagan,
but he would have been an exceedingly bad Pagan. There
was no world which held more stringently the idea of civic
responsibility than the ancient world, the world of Hellenism.
Again, one may ask, why should Hebraism be regarded
as the expression of a dark self-effacement; why should
the Hebrews be regarded as a gloomy people? They
danced openly with delight in the goodness of God; the
key-word of the Old Testament from beginning to end is
the word "joy." Their sacred books blaze with gold and
jewels just as they blaze with elemental gratitude and
pleasure. They believe, more openly and professedly than
any people has believed, in the primal fertilities, in the
fact that the corn and the orchard are the signals of the
ultimate beneficence, in the fact that children and the fruit
of the womb are a heritage and gift that cometh of the
Lord. They declared that God called all things good, the
most stupendously daring thing that any people has ever
said. Yet they said one thing more daring still; they said
that all things called God good, that the blessing of the
Seventh Day was hurled back again upon the Giver, that
all created things praised the Lord. If this be the situation, it is at least striking. God declares that the leper
is good, and the leper praises God in reply. It would cause
no astonishment if such a people was accused of extravagant optimism, of grotesque exuberance, of hysterical
hilarity. But that they should be accused of being sombre, and allowing no place for exhilaration, is perhaps one of
the darkest and most ancient riddles of human stupidity.
It is absolutely and genuinely, for all intellectual purposes,
like accusing the French of a slow and heavy materialism,
or the Vikings of an over-subtle aestheticism.
Upon the whole, it would seriously appear that in
setting the Jew to fight the Greek in the lists of philosophy we
have created a brutal and unmeaning conflict. We have made
a war out of nothing as coolly and as cruelly as if we had
set one cock to fight another cock in an ordinary cock-pit.
There is no conflict between the culture of the Greeks and
the religion of the Jews, when each is carried to its own
natural and necessary culmination. The Greeks were a
great deal too cultured to disapprove of religion. The Jews
were a great deal too religious to be ignorant of pleasure.
The real difference between them was not anything so futile
as the distinction involved in the common use of the words
Hellenism and Hebraism. The difference between them
was not that the Greeks had a culture so limited that it never
looked to the needs of the spirit, or that the Jews had a
religion so self-contradictory that it never praised God for
corn or wine or children. The real difference was in what
may be called the pulse or pace of belief. The Greek polytheism exhibited in an admirable symbolic form a sense of
the doubt and vagueness of existence, the sense that one
thing calls us one way and one another, that one God bids
us go on and another God bids us turn back. The Jewish
monotheism expressed the idea of the passionate unity and
impetus of all things, that one God calls us, by one trumpet-call, to the observance of one law. The gods of the Greeks are alien even when they are benevolent: they are often, in
Greek poetry, the enemies of their best adorers. The God
of the Jews is a party leader, who never fails his friends, because he and they have one great cosmic triumph to
achieve. The life of man, according to the Greeks, is a
manly and steadfast march in a wilderness. According to
the Jews, it is a cavalry charge of tree, brute, beast, and
man, and it matters nothing if a thousand fail, if the charge
carries the walls of Chaos.
No comments:
Post a Comment
Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.